Belding: Government shouldn’t take guns; participation is true source of freedom, not Bill of Rights
April 25, 2011
Judging from the feedback on my column from
last week, in the process of commenting on the Second Amendment, I
apparently said and indicated many things. This column
is to clarify my position on the issues of gun control, political
participation, the Second Amendment and the relationship between
the Bill of Rights and Constitution in general.
My analysis of the clauses of the Second
Amendment may be wrong, and I may disagree with various Supreme
Court decisions — especially recent ones — but it is not my belief,
nor did I ever mean to indicate, that the U.S. Constitution grants
the government to illegalize the ownership of firearms. I did not
attempt to “scuttle” the Second Amendment and explain how there is
no freedom granted in it; the idea was to define its legitimate
uses.
I think gun control is a bad idea. I think it
is bad policy to disarm law-abiding citizens and not allow them an
opportunity to defend themselves against criminal
attackers. Actions can only
be effectively opposed by actions. The police cannot
be everywhere, nor would we want them to be
everywhere, watching our every move. The United States
is not, nor ever was, a police state. At the time of
the American Revolution, that was one of the British liberties we
prized. In contradistinction to states such as France, Spain and
Russia, the British empire was not a police
state.
It is citizens, individuals, must be the first
defenders of their lives and property against
criminals. They are there,
on the scene, and actually have a vested, personal
interest in making sure the crime about to happen does not go
forward. Restrictions on who can purchase firearms,
such as minors and persons with certain health issues, and their
ownership, should probably require classes on how to use them
properly and how to safely store them. But the right
to possess a firearm should not be completely removed, nor made so
difficult as to be nonexistent.
And when I say that the right to bear arms is
a collective right, I do not mean something socialist, communist,
fascist or totalitarian.
To state the fact that “well-regulated” meant
“well-trained” simply proves my own point. Training is
not achieved by one’s own initiative; not uniform training, anyway,
of the kind necessary for any military body to be
effective. No, that training must come from
government.
However, politics should not be done with
guns. And that was the whole point of last week’s
column. Force should never
be used, by left or right, to accomplish political
aims. Whether that force be
done by rioting groups or crazed individuals, it has no place in a
reasonable discourse concerning matters to be decided upon by our
political institutions; by our representative
bodies.
Political participation at even the most local
levels of government was widespread in British America before the
Revolution. The
Constitution of 1787 created yet another level of government in
which people could participate. The Constitution, in
fact, assumes that American citizens will be active in their
governments. In order for it to work, Americans must
vote regularly in the election of their
representatives.
They must, in fact, do more than
that. They must discuss the issues among themselves
and inform themselves on those subjects that are matters of public
concern.
The right “to alter or to abolish” oppressive
governments is indeed affirmed in the Declaration of
Independence. But nowhere
does that document state that forceful action is acceptable in
political matters. In fact, the document complains of the removal
of Americans from political decision making by the British
government.
It is because the British were making laws for
us — without us, not including us in a political process in which
we were interested — that we declared our independence, not mere
discontentedness at the substance of those laws.
And the Constitution that resulted from that
revolution is not a social contract. Before the Bill of Rights was
added to it, it created a set of institutions through which we
agreed, as citizens, to solve our problems. There is no need to
protect the right “to alter or to abolish” our government, because
the citizens of America are the government. If people
would participate in the institutions which the Constitution — both
of the U.S. and the state governments — their freedoms would not be
in jeopardy. Corrupt representatives are the effect,
not the cause, of a corrupt people.
It is for this reason that a Bill of Rights
was opposed and cautioned against by the author of “The Federalist
Papers” and other writers who commented on the Constitution during
the debates on its ratification. A Bill of Rights,
making the government into a social contract, would outsource the
protection of rights to a piece of paper, not effective, positive
action by real people.
Such agreements are the enumeration of
“certain immunities and modes of proceeding, which are relative to
personal and private concerns, according to Federalist No.
84. In other words,
they are made with respect to private affairs, not public matters,
and are not the substance of political unions.
Hamilton viewed a Bill of Rights as
unnecessary and, in fact, irrelevant because of the system
established by the Constitution. He wrote in
Federalist No. 84, “It is evident, therefore, that, according to
their primitive signification, they have no application to
constitutions, professedly founded upon the power of the people and
executed by their immediate representatives and
servants. Here, in
strictness, the people surrender nothing; and as they retain
everything they have no need of particular reservations.”
In other words, inclusion of a Bill of Rights
was a poor idea because no power to take away the rights enumerated
there existed in the Constitution itself. Hamilton’s
view rests on the understanding that the Constitution is one which
establishes a state where citizens will participate in the
government of their country and assume an active public role for
themselves.
A Bill of Rights, therefore, is exactly the
opposite of the kind of Constitution established in 1787. The
Constitution, Hamilton wrote in Federalist No. 84, “is
merely intended to regulate the general political interests of the
nation,” and is not concerned with “the regulation of every species
of personal and private concerns.”
The Constitution of 1787, in its own right,
accomplishes one of the goals of a Bill of Rights: that is,
according to Federalist
No. 84, “to declare and specify the political privileges of
the citizens in the structure and administration of the
government.”
It is ultimately up to citizens, not solemn
words on paper, to safeguard freedom. The fact that a person
believes the Second Amendment provides no security for your “right”
to use force in exercising your political liberties does not mean
that he believes the government can take your guns or keep you from
lawfully exercising your right of self-defense.